Free download. Book file PDF easily for everyone and every device. You can download and read online Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics file PDF Book only if you are registered here. And also you can download or read online all Book PDF file that related with Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics book. Happy reading Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics Bookeveryone. Download file Free Book PDF Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics at Complete PDF Library. This Book have some digital formats such us :paperbook, ebook, kindle, epub, fb2 and another formats. Here is The CompletePDF Book Library. It's free to register here to get Book file PDF Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics Pocket Guide.
What is Kobo Super Points?

What are VitalSource eBooks? For Instructors Request Inspection Copy. We provide complimentary e-inspection copies of primary textbooks to instructors considering our books for course adoption. Most VitalSource eBooks are available in a reflowable EPUB format which allows you to resize text to suit you and enables other accessibility features. Where the content of the eBook requires a specific layout, or contains maths or other special characters, the eBook will be available in PDF PBK format, which cannot be reflowed.

For both formats the functionality available will depend on how you access the ebook via Bookshelf Online in your browser or via the Bookshelf app on your PC or mobile device. Stay on CRCPress. Preview this Book. Add to Wish List. Corner, A. The psychological mechanism of the slippery slope argument. Journal of Memory and Language, 64 , — Gardner, W. Can human genetic enhancement be prohibited? The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 20 , 65— Govier, T. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 12 , — Holtug, N. Human gene therapy: Down the slippery slope.

Julia Tanner (Durham University): Publications - PhilPeople

Bioethics, 7 5 , — Kneale, W. The development of logic. Launis, V.


  • BBC - Ethics - Introduction to ethics: The slippery slope?
  • Article Sidebar.
  • The Philosophical Baby: What Childrens Minds Tell Us about Truth, Love & the Meaning of Life;
  • Slippery Slope.
  • Download options.

Human gene therapy and the slippery slope argument. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 5 2 , — Rachels, J. The end of life. Resnik, D. The Sanctity of Life ethic is usually founded on religious, and specifically Christian, thinking. For Sanctity of Life theorists and supporters as described in this section, problems with the quality of a life never undermine the ultimate value and worth of a life.

A non-religious person may prefer to speak of an absolute right to life that cannot be taken away through non-voluntary euthanasia, and cannot be revoked by personal decree in the context of voluntary euthanasia. However, more often, the view is supported by Biblical reference. Linking the Sanctity of Life view to both abortion and euthanasia, Mother Teresa gave a statement of the appeal of this ethical stance:.

For me, life is the most beautiful gift of God to mankind, therefore people and nations who destroy life by abortion and euthanasia are the poorest. A Catholic Declaration of Faith is clear and absolute in nature:. For it is a question of the violation of the divine law, an offence against the dignity of the human person, a crime against life, and an attack on humanity. No legislator, guided by moral ideals, can ever morally recommend this type of killing, whether motivated by a mistaken sense of mercy or not.

Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics

Let us return to the Catholic Declaration of Faith. The document states that:. This does not mean that Christians oppose palliative care a type of care that does not attempt to extend life, so much as make an individual as comfortable as possible as they face the end of their life. However, it does explain why a life should be seen through to its natural end and why it might therefore be viewed as morally wrong to shorten it.

This objection does not require any view regarding the Sanctity of Life or a deontological duty not to kill; indeed, the slippery slope objection is both teleological in nature and does not even require a denial that euthanasia might be desirable in certain instances when viewed in the abstract or in isolation. To see the strength of such an objection, consider earlier pro-euthanasia arguments couched in terms of resource allocation and personal autonomy. After all, if you are a teleologist perhaps, an act utilitarian you have already given up ideas concerning absolute rules against certain actions.

It therefore may be objected that either life is sacred, or it is not, and if it is not then we may end up in a situation we find utterly morally indefensible even if we start from apparently moral motivations. Most people might view such enabling of suicide for patients with mental health needs as being very different from euthanasia for PVS patients or the terminally ill, but if personal autonomy justifies euthanasia then how can we justifiably draw a strong enough line so as to allow some people to choose death, but not others?

Cookies on the BBC website

Again, it may be objected that either personal autonomy matters or it does not. If we enable a person to have their life ended, then it is obvious they can never come to a different view on the value of their life at a later stage, as they might have had they still been alive. If non-voluntary euthanasia is granted, and a legal, moral and cultural line in the sand is thereby crossed, may not elderly patients feel pressured to not be a burden to their families? May not the financially well-off elderly feel pressure to allow their children to inherit any accumulated wealth rather than see that wealth spent on their own care?

Granting non-voluntary euthanasia in even a small number of cases may, over time, send us down a slippery slope to the non-morally defensible euthanising of many other types of patients who, as things stand, are quite content to remain alive since they have no reason to consider other options. Why think of negative consequences from a change in the law, when these consequences might not happen? Indeed, some slippery slope arguments are logical fallacies if they are premised on the idea that a possible negative outcome must, of necessity, follow from some change in policy.

The slippery slope objection suggests that the negative outcomes might be probable, rather than be certain. Thus, a response should deal with the issue of probable negative consequences, rather than cheapening a plausibly reasonable objection through wilful misrepresentation of its structure. Researching the situation in Belgium, where the law regarding euthanasia is perhaps the most liberal in the world, should provide a good grounding to either support or oppose this line of thought, as would considering the application of Rule Utilitarianism.

This objection brings together two distinct, but relevantly similar, lines of thought. Firstly, it might be suggested that to euthanise those who are terminally ill, or those in a PVS, is to kill people earlier than would otherwise happen and thereby to artificially eliminate their chances of living to experience a cure to their condition.

suppdebuhul.ga At the very least, if not a cure, euthanised people are not around to benefit from any step-forward in treatment that might alleviate their suffering. It might be thought plausible that a person with a severe and worsening disease who is not euthanised could have their condition and pain carefully managed by skilled healthcare professionals so as to greatly diminish any suffering. However, he urges that:. Against a very small number of unnecessary deaths that might occur if euthanasia is legalised we must place the very large amount of pain and distress that will be suffered if euthanasia is not legalised, by patients who really are terminally ill.

Join our email club...

Whether or not palliative care is able to reduce suffering to the extent suggested by the objection is something you may wish to consider and further research, as it would seem to be an empirical claim requiring contemporary evidence to further the discussion. The distinction between active and passive euthanasia is thought to be crucial for medical ethics.

The idea is that it is permissible, at least in some cases, to withhold treatment and allow a patient to die, but it is never permissible to take any direct action designed to kill the patient. This doctrine seems to be accepted by most doctors.


  • Join Kobo & start eReading today.
  • Down the Slippery Slope: Arguing in Applied Ethics?
  • Arguments in contemporary debates on bioethics.
  • Jan Karons Mitford Years: The First Five Novels (A Mitford Novel).

Recall from the chapter on Natural Law ethics that one of the primary precepts for human beings is the preservation of life. A secondary precept, derived from this primary precept, would certainly seem to deny the moral acceptability of artificial shortening of life. However, Natural Law theorists are able to to have a nuanced stance in the euthanasia debate. If an act is directed by a desire to do moral good, yet has a foreseeable but unintended consequence of a bad effect, then this action may be moral so long as the bad effect was not aimed at, does not outweigh the good effect and is not directly the cause of the bad itself.

If this brief comment is unclear, it is critical to look back to the relevant discussion of the Doctrine of Double Effect in the chapter on Natural Law. A doctor may be aware that a patient has not long to live and is suffering immensely. The doctor may prescribe a multitude of painkillers to treat the pain, even though this will have the foreseeable but unintended effect of killing the patient as a result of the side-effects of the drugs. Indeed, a doctor may simply refrain from offering painful treatment methods in order to avoid causing suffering, with the unintended but foreseeable consequence that the patient will die as a result of the non-intervention.

These actions are not morally wrong, says the Natural Law theorist, because death is not intended directly but rather the morally good end of pain reduction is intended directly. Rachels says that:. This outcome is good and motivates bosses to act to save money on their recycling bill, with the foreseeable but unintended consequence of polluting a local river. If we would not excuse the company for ignoring a foreseeable consequence, says Singer, then we do not really believe we escape responsibility for allowing death in the euthanasia context.